334 research outputs found

    A Comment on Text, Time and Audience Understanding in Constitutional Law

    Get PDF

    The Paths to Legal Equality: A Reply to Dean Sullivan

    Get PDF

    Foreward: The Most Confusing Branch

    Get PDF

    Identity Politics and the Second Amendment

    Get PDF

    What Does the Second Amendment Mean Today?

    Get PDF
    A growing body of scholarship argues that the Second Amendment protects a right of individuals to possess firearms, regardless of whether those individuals are organized in state militias. Proponents of the individual right view do not merely disagree with those who champion the competing view that the Second Amendment poses few if any obstacles to most forms of gun control legislation by the state or federal governments. They appear to believe that the Second Amendment has been subject to uniquely shabby treatment by the courts and, until recently, academic commentators. This Article argues that the Second Amendment has not been unfairly orphaned. The courts and commentators that reject the individual right scholars\u27 claims are justified in doing so by the application of the same criteria of interpretation commonly applied to other constitutional provisions, including: doctrine; text; original understanding; structural inference; post-adoption history; and normative considerations. In contrast to the individual right view, under the collective right interpretation, the Second Amendment protects some right of state militias against undue federal interference but no right of individuals against either federal or state regulation. This Article is sympathetic to the collective right view but acknowledges that the Second Amendment is, and has always been, somewhat puzzling. Motivated in large measure by the Founders\u27 distrust of standing armies, even on the broadest reading, the Second Amendment does nothing to prevent the federal government from maintaining a standing army. So, too, the right of rebellion that has served as the principal normative justification for a right to possess firearms has been emphatically rejected by our constitutional history

    The Morality of Prophylactic Legislation (with Special Reference to Speed Limits, Assisted Suicide, Torture, and Detention Without Trial)

    Get PDF
    My subject is the morality of prophylactic legislation. What do I mean by ‘prophylactic’ legislation? Let me illustrate the concept by drawing a contrast with the most famous hypothetical case in the scholarly literature of Anglo-American jurisprudence. During the course of their debate over the relation between law and morality, Lon Fuller and H. L. A. Hart disagreed about what tools are needed to discern the meaning and scope of a rule barring vehicles from a public park. Hart and Fuller clashed over whether legislative purpose and considerations of morality enter into the process of discerning what Hart famously called the ‘core of settled meaning’. They themselves did not disagree about the fact that there will be cases at the margin of this and every rule, but the example has since come to illustrate the various positions one can take on marginal applications, especially the following question: when, if ever, should ambiguous statutory language be construed to reach circumstances that were not specifically contemplated by the legislature? My topic concerns the relation between law and morality, but in a somewhat different sense from the way in which Hart, Fuller, and others have mooted these issues. For one thing, I am interested in the question of whether a legislature ought to enact a law, not in how judges should construe laws once they are enacted. For another, I am setting aside the difficulty of unforeseen circumstances and focusing on problems to which the legislature accurately foresees the range of applications of its legislation, although not the identities of the individuals to whom it will apply. ‘Prophylactic legislation’, as I shall use the term, refers to laws that the legislature deliberately writes so as to cover not only cases presenting the mischief it targets, but also some cases in which the legislature knows that the law’s background justification fails. Why would a rational legislature deliberately write a law that applies to circumstances in which the law is unjustified? A legislature might rationally decide to over-extend its reach for a number of reasons. It might fear that a more narrowly targeted law would be under-inclusive, and that the dangers from under-inclusion outweigh those from over-inclusion. Or, as I shall elaborate in greater detail shortly, the legislature might choose an over-inclusive rule rather than a potentially better targeted standard, because the legislature worries that the standard would confer too much discretion on those who execute and interpret it. Thus, prophylactic legislation will often be rational but, I shall argue, it nonetheless raises profound moral questions whenever it jeopardizes fundamental interests for, by definition, it does so without sufficient justification in the circumstances to which the legislation’s background purpose does not apply. Whether the moral questions can be answered, I shall argue further, depends in large part on whether reasonable people behind a veil of ignorance could be expected to assent to the prophylactic legislation. I shall explore these questions using four principal examples: speed limits; assisted suicide; torture; and detention without trial

    No Federalists Here: Anti-Federalism and Nationalism on the Rehnquist Court

    Get PDF

    The Marginality of Citizens United

    Get PDF
    • …
    corecore